chemists and c1inical pharmacists. There is indeed enough to do for all ofus.
The progress in this field is easy to recognize for those of us who during the sixties
found ourselves in the situation of prescribing drugs that later were found to be
contributions to the understanding of pharmacokinetics are now part of the routine
work up ofthe fate ofnew drugs in man. Editors of c1inical pharmacological journals
are today 'begging' for papers eIucidating the c1inical relevance of all this new kinetic
information - an area where c1inical pharmacology should play a key-role by
designing better methods for assessing drug response .
There are many other challenges to c1inical pharmacological research.
Recent advances in pharmacogenetics with the demonstration of polymorphisms
in drug hydroxylation may open up new possibilities to identify rare individuals at
risk during long-term drug therapy. Future utilization oftissue banks in metabolism
studies may become feasible. Biochemical assessment ofdrug action in man is still in
its infancy c1inically. Receptor pharmacology has already provided new tools for
c1inical investigations. New methods have to be developed to assess the overall
effects, beneficial as weil as adverse, of drugs in general use outside the controlIed
These examples and past history show that c1inical pharmacology has a vigorous
research profile of its own, focussing on general drug problems and on drugs as
molecules rather than as remedies for particular diseases. The future of c1inical
pharmacological research has never been brighter.
Due to the complexities of drug research in man, particularly from the ethical
point of view, there is an increasing demand for a constructive and international
dialogue between scientists in drug control, pharmaceutical industry and academia.
The recent worries both in the US and UK about bureaucracy becoming a rate
limiting factor in drug development underline the key role that a strong, independent
academic c1inical pharmacology could play in trying to resolve this dilemma. As an
example should we not along with the tremendous developments in human kinetics
and drug metabolism require less extensive studies ofthe same kind in animals that at
the best reconfirm the existence of species differences in metabolism, binding and
While the contributions of c1inical pharmacology in research are evident, our
Data are now being collected from various countries in the world notably Australia,
Northern Europe, UK and the USA which show marked deviations in some drug
prescribing patterns from accepted pharrnacological principles (Turner, 1979). There
is a peculiar combination of under- and over-utilization of drugs. As an example, in
1976, drug problems (intoxications and drug abuse being excluded) were the main
reasons for over 10% of consecutive admissions to the medical wards of a university
hospital in Stockholm. Adverse drug reactions and inadequate treatment with drugs
including poor patient compliance with the regimen were equally important
International comparisons of drug prescribing have revealed astounding
differences that are difficult to explain in terms of geographical differences in
morbidity or other rational factors. The number of drug products available to the
prescribing physician may vary IO-fold between European countries with similar
socioeconomic and medical conditions. In an interview with Elliott (1979), William
G. Anlyan who directed the compilation ofthe Institute ofMedicine report on drug
prescribing in USA states, "T he medical profession needs to clean up its own house.
The most important goal we must set is to improve the quality of education in
clinical pharmacology at the med icaI school and residence level . . .' With the
constant manpower problem in clinical pharmacology we are not likel y to be able to
do much of this education ourselves. Rather we will have to develop the means of
getting our messages across through other educators in clinical medicine and other
health personnel. It is high time that drug prescribing and therapeutic principles
become dependent variables; and equally important, drug therapy must be assessed
in a general medical perspective and balanced against other therapeutic approaches
such as dietary treatment and psychotherapy.
The clinical pharmacologist has, therefore, an equally important role in informing
the medical community when drugs are needed and when they are not. A majority of
physicians in the developed countries and almost all in the developing countries still
get their prime continued drug education solely from industry, particularly from
detail men . This is far from satisfactory. Clinical pharmacology should get into the
medical curriculum in all medical schools not as an elective extravagance but as a
tough required course. And I cannot see why the pedagogic influence of clinical
pharmacology on ph ysicians should stop when they start prescribing drugs . Clinical
pharmacologists cannot afford to close their doors to the real world of drug
For a new discipline, striving for international recognition, collaboration within
and between countries is essential. We have a forum for international collaboration
through the section of Clinical Pharmacology in IUPHAR. Founded in 1975 this
Section has as its key priorities to facilitate training and to develop training
programmes in clinical pharmacology and to serve as a consulting body for
individuals and organizations interested in the discipline.
On behalf of the Section of Clinical Pharmacology I wish to extend our cordial
thanks to the organizers of thi s conference, particularly Professor Colin Dollery and
Professor Alasdair Breckenridge and their close associates, for having given us the
opportunity to come to London for th is meeting. It will be an important milestone in
establishing clinical pharmacology world wide as an indispensable branch of
Bergman, U. & Wiholm, B. E. (1980). Drug related problems causing admission to a medical
c1inic. Eur. J. clin. Pharmac.. in press.
Breckenridge, A. M. (1980). Assessment of new drugs: a c1inical pharmacologist's view. Brit.
Carr, E. A. (1963). Proposed aims, organization, and activities of a division of c1inical
pharmacology. Clin. Pharmac. Ther.. 4, 587-595.
Crout, J. R. (1965). Academic clinical pharmacology and the university medical center.
Dollery, C. T. (1966). C1inical pharmacology.Lancet. 1, 359-360.
Elliott,J. (1979). Physician prescribingpracticescriticized; solutions in question. Medica! Ne ws.
J. Am. med. Ass.. 241,2353-2360.
Gross, F. (1978). The thorny path ofclinical pharmacology. Clin. Pharmac. Ther.. 24, 383-394.
Lasagna, L. (1962). Profession, governmentand drug industry. Lancet,1,580-581.
Lasagna, L. (1966). C1inical pharmacology: present status and futuredevelopment. Science, 152,
Turner, P. (1979). A clinical pharmacologist's view.Lancet, 2, 735.
WardeIl, W. M. (1970). C1inical pharmacology at university medical centers: functions and
organization. J. clin. Pharmac.. 14, 309-324.
Wilson, G. M. (1963). Difficulties and opportunities in clinical pharm acology. Clin. Pharmac.
World Health Organization (1969). Clinical pharmacology. Scope organization, training.
Report of a WHO study group. World Health Organization Technical Report Series No.
Department ofPharmacology and Toxicology,
A cyn ic has described regulation as the substitution of error for chance. Be that as it
Both science and ethics are time- and culture-bound. One century's science is
another century's quackery, and what is ethical for one society is not necessarily so
for another society, or even for the sa me society at a later date . Beecher (1966), who
initiated a world-wide revul sion against unethical investigators with his article, had
for years performed experiments on human subjects (both healthy volunteers and
patients) without obtaining informed consent. The evolution in this century of the
randomized controlled trial has made it impossible to return to earlier times, when
on unvalidated in vitro tests is no longer scient ifrcally defen sible .
never be troubled with having to think whether this ought to be done or not, it should
be settled by rules . . . . Plainly, the more rules you can invent, the less need there will
be to waste time over fruitless puzzling about right and wrong.' This witty man
added, 'Ever y public action wh ich is not customary, either is wrong, or, ifit is right , is
a dangerous precedent. It follows that nothing should ever be done for the first time. '
humans. The search for such ehernieals is based on unmet medical needs, that is,
illness not optimall y served by available medicines. There is little likelihood that
science will run out of motivation in this regard in the fore seeable future . No
significant disease or symptom now exists for which more effective or less toxic
remedies are not desired by the public or the medical profession.
But predicting what chemical will be a 'better' drug poses serious difficulties, since
our subhuman models and in vitro tests are never completely isomorphic with the
educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of
There are, to be sure, limits imposed upon us by reality. No drug developer can
afford to run all the screening tests that could possibly be imagined, or study
thousands of animals of many different species, searching for extremely rare adverse
effects. The ethical posture, hence, is to perform those tests in numbers and with a
completeness that are consistent with a functional drug development programme.
We can neither cut corners recklessly nor shun the heavy responsibility for fmding
Once it is decided that cautious exploration of a drug in man is justified, a new
How shall one ca1culate the first doses to be given to man?
How many subjects are to be studied in Phase I?
Are these first subjects to be healthy volunteers, or sick patients?
At what rate ofprogression shall the dose be increased?
What variables should be measured?
How shall the doses be chosen for the first clinical trials (Phase II)?
How much additional toxicity testing will be required as clinical trials increase in
scope, as drug dosage is increased in amount or in duration ofadministration, or as
new kinds ofsubjects are put at risk?
These questions, it will be noted, involve both ethical and scientific considerations.
For these reasons, protocols proposed for human studies deserve to be scrutinized
critically by review boards with a membership capable of dealing with both levels of
concern. AJatally flawed experimental design is unethical because it puts subjects at
risk with no possibility of'benefit to anyone. Individuals other than thc invcstigators
should decide whether a proposed experiment is too dangerous to be done .
their senses should be allowed to make their own decisions about participating in
dangerous experiments, and that censorship of experimentation carries its own risks,
science in general has to beware the harm that can accrue to all investigators by lurid
publicity attendant on research that strikes the public as (or worse, that turns out to
be) needlessly risky . In asense, all scientists owe it to their guild to protect the public
image ofscience by avoiding research that will give it a black eye.:
So far as consent is concerned, I see no great theoretical problems in regard to
providing information to healthy volunteers. Such subjects deserve a full explanation
of what is planned by the investigator, including the purpose of the experiment, its
anticipated benefits, and the possible risks. Some have argued that informed consent
information that one cannot ever anticipate everything which might possibly happen.
This uncertainty should be appreciated by potential subjects in addition to their
comprehending the available facts. There is a problem with regard to the mode of
presentation. Our own works (Epstein & Lasagna, 1969) has shown that there is
danger of information overload in obtaining consent from subjects. Excessive detail
may actually impede communication, and it cannot be assumed that exposure to
information is tantamount to comprehension.
ETHICAL AND SCIENTIFIC BASIS OF REGULATION 5
the physician ofrecord for a patient subject. People who oppose the use ofstudents or
prisoners in research often seem to ignore the much greater likelihood of a 'captive'
status for the patient approached by his doctor to take an investigational drug. It
must be made clear to any patient who is asked to participate in research that medical
care or the patient-doctor relationship will not be jeopardized by failure to volunteer
or by withdrawal at any time after the experiment begins.
is 'enough' reward for healthy volunteers or patients. Rewards should not, it has been
said, be so extraordinary as to be coercive per se in seducing volunteers who would
decided that an experiment can be conducted ethically, adequacy of compensation
should be a matter for agreement between the parties involved.
If harmed as a result of research participation, subjects deserve compensation for
medical care, for lost time from work or horne, or for irreparable damage. Society
needs mechanisms for compensation that are equitable but not punitive, barring
negligence on the part ofsponsor or investigator.
It is unethical to perform aseries ofclinical trials that are simply repetitions ofwell
done experiments that have demonstrated beyond question that a chemical produces
a desirable specific therapeutic efTect. Some repetition is a fundamental tenet of
science, but going beyond enough repetition to assure reasonable scientists that the
efTect is real represents regulatory overkill and immorality. Some local experience is
no doubt desirable, but this need not be in the nature of double-blind, randomized
Recently, Burkhardt 800-Kienle (1978) have proposed that all controlled clinical
trials are unethical, illegal , or both, because the null hypothesis is really not seriously
entertained by the investigator even at the outset. In fact , this statement about the
null hypothesis is generally true: scientists pick drugs for human trial because they
strongly (and often correctly) suspect that the drug will be efTective. It is not clear,
however, that it is automatically unethical to do such trials, provided that patients
are fully informed and not subject to serious risk, since qualitative expectations about
a drug need to be fleshed out quantitatively, as to both benefit and harm. One can,
however, agree that as we deal with increasingly serious disease states or as we
develop increasingly better standard drugs, it is imperative that proposed research be
scrutinized with greater and greater care, not only justifying the choice of control
(placebo or standard drug) but also the decision to perform any experiment with a
drug candidate in humans. In a way, we are trapped by our own ingenuity, As our
standard drugs approach perfection, we will have an ever more difficult task in taking
new ones into clinical trial. It is clear, of course, that we are not even close to this
ethical and medical difficulties involved in the latter, but for future generations of
impressive and cogent evidence, but useful drugs are not necessarily 'better' on
average than standards. (They may be able to treat certain patients uniquely weil,
either by providing more therapeutic efTect or less adverse effect.) We shall simply
have to devote more energy to devising techniques that will get us off the horns of
these ethical dilemmas. (Some are already available, such as dose-response curves as
areplacement for placebo controls.) We may have to re-examine the utility ofclinical
data, that are not ofthe controlIed, randomized variety.
.Sequential designs allow one to perform c1inical trials with smaller sam pie size, on
average, than fixed-sample size trials. These designs have not become very popular,
for a variety of reasons, but they have much to ofTer in the study of patients who
sufTer from very rare diseases or from diseases where ineffective treatment will be
seriously deleterious. It has been proposed that c1inical trials should not be
terminated until 'administratively significant' difTerences between treatments are
observed (Buncher, 1973). To quote Buncher (1973): '.. . [al fmding should be
declared 'adrninistratively significant' only after .. . the likelihood that cxposure of
additional patients to the trial will persuade many physicians to adopt the better
therapy is so small that it is outweighed by the risks to the patients continuing in the
trials.' The point of this argument is that if a study is terminated prematurely, its
impact will be small or nil and the trial will have been performed in vain. Some
serious problems exist with regard to this approach. One is that it is difficult (if not
impossible) to know what will convince others. 'Statistical significance' not only
poscs the need to pick some level of confidence, but ignores the fact that statistically
significant and biologically significant difTerences are not necessarily the same. A
second problem is that an investigator should terminate a trial when he is personally
desire more information than they have received in the past about their diseases and
is not easy to come up with such materials that are adequate for all patients and all
occasions. Patients difTer in age, intelligence, education, language skills, attitudes,
and many other factors. There is disagreement about the purpose ofsuch materials:
should the y be primarily warnings, or balanced presentations of benefrts and risks?
Who should administer the materials? Should there be flexibility in both materials
and mode of presentation? How does one keep these materials up to date? The area
cries for research before widespread implementation of the use of new educational
Scientifically, regulation needs a data base that will allow the responsible agency to
make a judgement that, with proper directions, physicians will be able to use the drug
so that treated patients will reap more benefrt than harm. This global or group
judgment is really the only one that can be made. It is fruitless to search for more
precision than this, although we must insure that enough c1inical and preclinical data
exist to make this importantjudgment, and that we havc a reasonable idea as to how
to write directions for the physician that will encourage flexibility of treatment
depending on c1inical variables ofhuman importance.
In my view , it does not take a tremendous amount of c1inical work to identify a
useful drug or to delineate its more common side efTects. There are , however,
formidable problems if we try to an swer in advance of marketing all the questions
that might possibly be raised:
What special adverse efTects occur after years ofcontinued treatment for medicines
ETHI CAL AN D SCIE NTIFI C BASIS OF REG ULATIO N 7
What very rare but serious toxic effects will be seen?
What interactions (beneficial or harmful) will occur between the drug and other
prescription or proprietary remed ies?
What interactions will be seen between dru g and disease, such as renal or hepat ic
What special hazards will exist for the foetuses oftreated pregnant women? For the
Will the new medicine be abu sed by segments of the popul ation , either for addi ction or suicide?
In thinking about these que stion s, society must balance costs against benetits.
Not onl y will pati ents suffer thereby, but economic incentives will disappear. New
chemical entities already cost many mill ions of dollars and years ofwork to reach the
market. Effective pat ient life shrinks yearly, on average , as a consequence of the
Th e most rational policy, I submit, is to plan carefully for many ofthese quest ions
to be an swered with appropriate speed after registration. Society must judge which
question s must be answered befor e marketing, as weil as tho se that must be attacked
Thi s will mean post-marketing studies that are more than simply attempts to study
poorly in large numbers ofpatients what has been weil studied in more modest trials.
It is, however, extremely pertinent to search for new information, both good and bad,
about a new medicine , including very rare or long dela yed toxicity, although the
latt er concerns are just tho se that science is least weil equipped to identify. We also
preventable , as opposed to tho se that ar e not.
Post-registration respon sibilit y also include s the application oftechn iques that will
detect qual ity control problems at the manufacturing level, and the use of registers
(for example, of congen ital defects or cancers) that may l1ag a probl em becau se of
temporal changes in prevalenc e ofabnormalities that might possibly be drug-related.
Let me, fmally, return to my first theme - the need to keep reviewing our scientific
and eth ical bases for regulation as the world change s. The skyrocketing costs of drug
development have, for example, decreased the likelihood that unprofitable drugs (for
patients suffering from rare diseases) will reach the market. Society must come to
grips with this issue, and decide either that it reall y does not care about 'orphan drug'
problems, or that it will take regulatory and economic steps to allev iate it. One
approach may be a radically different level of demands for data on a drug intended
for a very few individuals who might weil be willing to take a unique remed y for a
serious disea se even without the safeguards usually demanded ofa new drug .
A second example is the proliferation of laboratory tests for carcinogenicity,
mutagenicity, and teratogenicity. These tests are in some cases easier to perform than
to interpret. How do we deal, scientifically and ethically, with an Ames test result ?
This test is far quicker and easier to perform reliably than an epidemiological study
to see whether saccharin use is associated with bladder cancer, but the latter may be
more to the point. What sort of in vitro or animal toxicity should justify 'killing' a
therapeutic agent? How much such data does one requ ire for action earl y in the
histor y of a drug's development? How much data after apparently satisfactory use of
a drug for years? How do we balance evidence ofmutagenicity in bacteria again st the
potential of a chem ical for treating the sick, realizing that the earlier a drug is ' killed',
the less we will know about its potential for good as weil as for harm?
00 our statistical ground rules need changing as our technology and science
increase in sophistication? There never has been an ything magical about 'P = 0.05 '
values, yet regulators tend to look upon this barrier as the statistical equivalent ofthe
Magie Fire that Wotan threw up around Brunhilde. Should the level ofconfidence be
set flexibl y, to deal with the very different sorts of conditions for which med icines are
intended? Is a two-tailed test justifiable in view of the overwhelming likelihood, for
mo st rernedies, that a new drug will 'outperforrn' the placebo, both therapeutically
and to xicologically? I am weil aware ofthe arguments for and against one-tailed tests.
There are relatively few case s where I personally feel so cocky that I am unwilling to
accept as real a very large difference in the unexpected direction. As Burke (1953)so
wittily pointed out: 'We counsel an yone who contemplates a on e-tailed test to ask of
himself (before the data are gathered): 'If my results are in the wrong direction and
significant at the one-billionth of 1% level, can I publicly defend the proposition that
this is evidence of no difference?' Ifthe answer is affirmative, we shall not impugn his
accuracy in choosing a one-tailed test. We may, however, question his scientific
I do not expect agreement on the answers to those questions, but I respectfully
submit that if we are to defend our scientific and ethical postures toward drug
regulation, we must keep asking ourselves about them. Science and morality have not
remained static in centuries past; it is difficult to see how they can avoid change in the
Beecher,H. K. (1966). Ethics and c1inical research. New Eng. J. Med.. 274, 1354-1360.
Buncher, C. R. (1973). Administratively significant. New Eng. J. Med., 289,155.
Burke, C.J. (1953). Abriefnote on one-tailed tests. Psych. Bull., 50, 384-387.
Burkhardt, R. & Kienle, G. (1978). Controlled c1inical trials and medical ethics. Lancet, 2,
No comments:
Post a Comment
اكتب تعليق حول الموضوع